|
|
Journal of Cosmology, 2009, Vol 2, pages 221-229 In PRESS Cosmology, October 8, 2009 The Cronus Hypothesis Extinction as a Necessary and Dynamic Balance to Evolutionary Diversification Corey J. A. Bradshaw, Ph.D. 1,2 and Barry W. Brook, Ph.D.1 1The Environment Institute and School of Earth and Environmental Sciences, University of Adelaide, Adelaide, South Australia 5005, Australia 2South Australian Research and Development Institute, P.O. Box 120, Henley Beach, South Australia 5022, Australia The incredible diversity of life on Earth veils the tumultuous history of biodiversity loss over deep time. Six mass extinction events since the Cambrian species explosion (including the current Anthropocene), and many smaller extinction spasms, have terminated 99% of all species that have ever existed. Evolution and extinction, as universal processes, have been unified previously under James Lovelock's Gaia hypothesis, and most recently, under Peter Ward's Medea hypothesis. Gaia (the Greek Earth mother) posits that life on Earth functions like a single, self-regulating organism, whereas Medea (siblicidal wife of Jason of the Argonauts) describes instead a self-destructive feedback where life "seeks" to destroy itself. We argue that these contrasting views are actually extremes of a scale-invariant stability entropy spectrum of speciation and extinction for all life on Earth, much as the abundance and stability of a metapopulation of an individual species is the emergent property of births, deaths and migration. In this context, we propose a new metaphor called the Cronus hypothesis (patricidal son of Gaia) to explain how these processes can be quantified with existing mathematical tools and so be used to describe the ebb and flow of life on Earth along a thermodynamic spectrum. We also argue that Cronus provides a broader framework with which to link the natural history research domains of evolutionary, ecological and extinction biology. For an evolutionary biologist to ignore extinction is probably as foolhardy as for a demographer to ignore mortality. David M. Raup (1994)
1. Introduction
Although the "background" extinction rate suggests that an average species' life span is approximately 1 10 million years (Frankham et al. 2002; Raup 1986), the pattern of deep-time extinctions is anything but constant. Mass extinction events have a variety of ultimate causes, from bolide impact to volcanism, and from marine anoxia to rapid climate change, some of which might have been the result of amplifying feedbacks arising from external catastrophic triggers such as an asteroid strike causing immediate mortality, short-term cooling from dimming atmospheric dust, and long-term warming from the carbon dioxide released from vast amounts of vaporised limestone (Alvarez 2003; Bambach 2006; Benton
2003; Conway-Morris 1997; Courtillot 1999; Erwin 2006; Gomez et al. 2007; Hallam 2005; Hallam & Wignall 1997; Hoffman 1989; Ward 1994). Despite early flirtations with the idea of regular return times (Raup & Sepkoski 1986), subsequent work has failed to confirm any detectable periodicity in extinction events (Benton 1995), and even species recovery post-event differs markedly (Conway-Morris 1998; Erwin 1998, 2001; Erwin 2006; Jablonski 1989; Raup 1991).
There is general consensus that we have now entered the sixth mass extinction event (Jones 2009; Sodhi et al. 2009), which has been dubbed the Anthropocene (Crutzen 2002) because its primary driver is human over-consumption, over-population, and associated degradation of the biosphere. This current biodiversity crisis (Ehrlich & Pringle 2008) is characterized by extinction rates exceeding the deep-time average background rate by 100- to 10000-fold (Pimm & Raven 2000), even though total species loss is still less than that during the largest deep-time mass extinctions (Gaston 2000; Pimm et al. 1995; Singh 2002; Smith et al. 1993). Although we have a growing comprehension of the principal drivers of extinction and their synergies (Bradshaw et al. 2008; Brook et al. 2008; Field et al. 2009; Purvis et al. 2000; Sodhi et al. 2008a; Sodhi et al. 2009; Sodhi et al. 2008b), our appreciation of its complexities is still rudimentary (Brook et al. 2008; Fagan & Holmes 2006; Melbourne & Hastings 2008).
Anyone not familiar with the intricacies of biotic extinction might perceive it to be a relatively direct and rapid process whereby all individuals making up the populations of a defined species are "removed" from the Earth by either direct exploitation, the sudden appearance of an alien predator, or the broad-scale destruction of habitats. However, the reality is that species disappear for a host of complex and interactive reasons (Brook et al. 2008; Melbourne & Hastings 2008), and the ultimate hammer driving the nail into a species' coffin is often not the same mechanism that caused it to decline in the first place (Brook et al.
2006; Caughley 1994). Some good examples of this mechanistic disconnect include the heath hen Tympanuchus cupido cupido (decline by over-harvesting; extinction from inbreeding depression, fire and predation Gross 1931; Johnson & Dunn 2006) and the great auk Pinguinus impennis (decline from hunting; extinction of the last remaining population by volcanic eruption Halliday 1978). Even the generally well-accepted idea that particular evolved traits heighten a species' extinction "proneness" are somewhat na๏ve because they ignore the circumstances under which these evolved via natural selection in the first place (Brook et al. 2008). Instead, it is the pace and character of environmental change (Brook et al. 2008; Sodhi et al. 2009) that leads to non-random rates and patterns of extinction among taxa (Jablonski 1989; Purvis et al. 2000). Given this context, we argue here that extinction is as integral a part of the history of life as speciation, and the two dynamic and interacting forces have traded blows over vast spans of time. This consistent interaction suggests to us a new way of contextualizing and modelling extinction within a broader biophysical framework. We term this new extinction-speciation trade-off the "Cronus hypothesis", which we describe in more detail below, and contrast it with existing concepts of global biodiversity patterns illustrated by the Gaia (Lovelock 2006), Medea (Ward 2009a,b) and entropy (Whitfield 2007) hypotheses.
Figure 1. The Cronus metaphor for the diversity of all planetary life, operating as an interacting and competing population of organisms. Cogs represent species assemblages (SA) of different composition and magnitude (e.g., number and type of species represented by variability in the number and shape of a cog's teeth). The organization of assemblages is similar to the stage structure of populations. Rates of speciation (SP) are analogous to [birth] in population models. Extinction of species (EXT) occurs within assemblages (or entire assemblages can disappear during mass extinction events) a process operating like mortality [death] of individuals in a population. Groups of species assemblages can interact within a single biogeographical realm as a sub-population within the global metapopulation, with different community composition (diversity, biomass, etc.) among realms (equivalent to sub-populations occupying areas of differing habitat suitability within a landscape). Realms are connected by dispersal and invasion operating over short (e.g., human-mediated invasion) or longer (e.g., continental plate tectonics; island colonization) time scales, processes analogous to [immigration & emigration] among sub-populations. Panspermia represents the hypothesized seeding of a primitive Earth by extraterrestrial microorganisms, potentially deriving from its own planetary metapopulation of organisms (Joseph 2009a,b).
We have chosen to call this framework, describing the global biota as a planetary population, the Cronus hypothesis. Cronus (Κρόνος) was the patricidal (or patri-emasculating) youngest son of Gaia, the Earth mother. Cronus was also the leader of the first generation of Titans, the giant descendants of Gaia and Uranus, the sky father. Cronus was incited by his mother to kill Uranus for perceived crimes against Gaia's other descendants, and Cronus himself was overthrown by his own son, Zeus, and banished to Hades (Atsma 2009). Given the tumultuous and competitive life-and-death history of Cronus, we believe this metaphor better captures the processes of inter-species competition and mutualisms that our population analogy of speciation and extinction embodies. Under the Gaia model, self-regulation works to avoid extinction because it is akin to the loss of a body part (function is reduced), whereas under Cronus, extinction is part of the process of natural selection (providing restoration of function through subsequent diversification).
We argue that the concept of Cronus has merit on two fronts. First, the notion of a community of species as a population of selfish individuals (Dawkins 1989) retains the Darwinian view of contestation, without the necessity of cooperation that the organismal Gaia concept implies. Self-regulation in Cronus occurs naturally as a result of extinction modifying the course of future evolution and opening up new opportunities for diversification to fill empty niches. Second, by regarding macroevolutionary forces as equivalent to population processes, deeper analogies emerge which are useful for scientific interpretation
of observed phenomena, and are amenable to mathematical manipulation using models developed for ecological lines of inquiry (Fig. 2). For instance, the causes of extinction can be thought of as equivalent to the different processes that lead to individual deaths within a population, be it from accidents (e.g., catastrophic extinctions from bolide strikes, volcanism, intense storms, wildfire; or chance demographic failure at low population size Melbourne & Hastings 2008), senescence (e.g., higher extinction probability in older phylogenetic lineages Johnson 1998; Lawton & May 1995; Nee & May 1997), conflict, starvation and disease (e.g., invasion of new competitors or predators [including humans], species-area effects following the biotic interchanges caused by continental drift, or fragmentation of habitats McKinney 1998), poison (e.g., oceanic hypoxia and acidification, increased atmospheric CO2), and even congenital defects (e.g., habitat specialization or large body size, leading to higher susceptibility of species to particular stressors Brook et al. 2008). Moreover, the differential mortality rates that are characteristic of the alternative life stages of many organisms can be compared to clades with low or high evolutionary turnover (Jablonski 1989).
Figure 2. The macro-domains of natural history. Under the Cronus metaphor for the dynamic ebb and flow of life on Earth as analogous to a population of organisms, evolutionary biology is the study of the "birth" rates and carrying capacity (selection balance) of species, and extinction biology is phylogenetic "death." Ecology envelopes the processes linking the temporal and spatial flux of biodiversity within the total physical environment (A). These major spheres contribute to, and acquire knowledge from, other fields of natural and environmental sciences such as molecular biology, chemistry and physical geography (B). Applied and theoretical disciplines such as conservation biology, paleontology, systematics and biogeography emerge from the nexus of these major fields (C), and exploit additional information from the broad realms of socio-economics, history and mathematics. Extinction both modifies, and is an outcome of, evolutionary processes (D). This schematic of the interrelationship of and interaction between research fields illustrates our major point that when the biology of extinction is perceived in the context of Cronus, it emerges quite naturally as a distinct and fundamental field of scientific inquiry which complements other major domains. To illustrate with a medical analogy, when a person dies, immediate interest focuses on what that individual loss has costs us (e.g., emotional impact, life insurance, loss of services they provided, etc.). This is akin to the applied discipline of conservation biology, which is concerned with preventing the loss of species on both intrinsic and utilitarian grounds (e.g., loss of ecosystem services). Yet when cancer or obesity death rates increase in a society, there is a need to understand and reduce broader causes through evidence-based epidemiological research. Cronus is the analytical framework that encapsulates equivalent lines of inquiry in extinction biology.
4. The Medea Hypothesis
We are not first to suggest an entirely new framework and metaphor for life on Earth since Gaia. Peter Ward (Ward 2009a,b) recently outlined a rather different perspective to Gaia and Cronus the Medea hypothesis. To extend the Greek mythology metaphor, the sorceress Medea (Μήδεια) was the granddaughter of Helios the sun god and wife to Jason of the Argonauts who later killed her own sons as revenge for Jason's unfaithfulness (Atsma 2009). Instead of the self-regulating super-organism Gaia, Ward describes the Earth's mass extinctions as Medean events large biodiversity loss driven by life itself (Ward 2009a). Arguing that the Gaia hypothesis cannot account for large shifts in the Earth's temperature
over geological time, Medea describes how the massive flux of atmospheric carbon dioxide and methane by the processes of plant, microbial and animal respiration was the very cause of such volatile conditions which lead to (at least some) mass extinctions (Ward 2009a,b). In essence, the Medean perspective describes a self-destructive, or anti-order component where life "seeks" to destroy itself, and it can do so on a massive scale due to amplifying feedbacks under certain circumstances (Ward 2009a,b). Modern human society might eventually merit the Medean soubriquet.
5. Entropy
The ideas of order and chaos alluded to above have spawned another way of looking at life (and death) on Earth. A concept gaining traction amongst evolutionary ecologists is the application of thermodynamic laws to models of evolution and extinction (Whitfield 2007). Directionality theory quantifies the rules governing the flow of metabolic energy between populations of competing individuals and environmental resources (Demetrius 2000). Thermodynamic models describe rules of heat energy transfer between aggregates of matter, so the family of parameters defining thermodynamics can be related formally to biotic patterns. Here, evolutionary entropy, a measure of heterogeneity in the age of reproducing individuals, is predicted to increase as a system evolves from one stationary state to the next, just as thermodynamic entropy increases for irreversible processes (Demetrius 2000). Entropy determines the rate of decay of fluctuations in abundance due to inherent demographic variability and increases in bounded populations over generations. Thus, extinction of species within a community can be considered a systematic loss of entropy, which results in reduced efficiency of energy flow and so leads to a decline in ecosystem stability (Whitfield 2007). Although such mathematical analogies currently have little direct empirical support, the application of physical laws to extinction dynamics demands more
attention, because it could provide a theoretical framework for predicting extinction patterns in the future.
What does this evolutionary zero-sum game of living matter portend for humanity? Most species on the planet today are rare in the sense that they are comprised of few individuals (Gaston 2008). Put another way, the state of commonness is unusual, and those few species that dominate total biomass do not tend to do so over the entire course of their evolutionary lifespan. In the current Anthropocene extinction event, even once-common species, such as the American bison (Bison bison) and passenger pigeon (Ectopistes migratorius), can decline to rarity or extinction (Gaston 2008; Gaston & Fuller 2008). What the future holds for the Earth's currently most common species, such as humans and their commensals, is uncertain, but the ideas of extinction and biomass-diversity constancy suggest that our time in the limelight of numerical dominance is limited (see Matheny 2007).
Figure 3. Three metaphors for the evolution, extinction and maintenance of life on Earth, named after figures from Greek mythology. Gaia represents order and self-regulation, whereas Medea is self-induced entropy loss. Our concept of Cronus bridges these extremes by considering the play-off between speciation (birth) and extinction (death) as a balanced product of these opposing tendencies. Gaia image from Attic Red Figure by Aristophanes ca. 410-400 BC (housed in Antikenmuseen, Berlin, Germany Berlin F2531, BAN: 220533; source: www.theoi.com). Cronus image from Attic Red Figure by the Nausicaa Painter ca. 475-425 BC (housed in Metropolitan Museum, New York, USA New York 06.1021.144, BAN: 214648; source www.theoi.com). Medea image from oil on canvas by Eug่ne Ferdinand Victor Delacroix 1862 (housed in Mus้e des Beaux-Arts, Lille, France).
7. Conclusion
Comparing these four ways of viewing life on Earth and beyond, and the opposing forces of speciation and extinction, our Cronus hypothesis and the thermodynamic framework of entropy loss are most similar and comprehensive both approaches allow for mathematical description of evolutionary forces, offset by extrinsic and intrinsic causes of species loss. In contrast, Lovelock's Gaia and Ward's Medea can be best viewed as extremes of a continuum between cooperation and self-destruction (i.e., Gaia versus anti-Gaia, or Gaia and her "evil twin" Ward 2009a), which ultimately require some intermediary process. As such, we posit that the background processes of natural history mostly operate closer to the centre of these extreme views (Fig. 3) that this is in fact the equilibrium and as such we argue that Cronus provides a better framework for explaining the patterns we observe in global biodiversity throughout most of the span of deep time (and space).
Analogous to Lovelock's parable of Daisyworld for applying a mathematical framework to the Gaia hypothesis (Lenton & Lovelock 2000; Watson & Lovelock 1983), a
Cronus view of evolutionary and extinction dynamics could be modelled by modifying existing metapopulation tools (Hanski 1998, 1999). For example, species as individuals with particular "mortality" (extinction) rates, and lineages with particular "birth"; (speciation) rates, could interact and disperse among "habitats' (biogeographical realms). "Density" feedback could represent anything from competitive exclusion to parasitic, mutualistic or commensal symbiosis. As a "population" (species) declines, perverse feedbacks such as inbreeding depression can induce Allee effects (Courchamp et al. 2008) that further exacerbate extinction risk this is one Medean-like phase of the population analogy represented by Cronus. In contrast, stochastic fluctuation around a "carrying capacity‟ (niche saturation; energy limitation) achieved through compensatory population dynamics arising when environmental conditions are relatively stable becomes the Gaia-like equilibrium embedded with Cronus. The Cronus model also has the advantage of being scale-invariant it could be applied to the turnover of microbial diversity inhabiting a single macro-organism through to inter-planetary exchange of life. When combined with more theoretical development (and, ideally, experimental or numerical testing) of the thermodynamic model of biological entropy, Cronus mathematics can be used by evolutionary ecologists, palaeontologists and exobiologists to pose and test novel hypotheses regarding the ever-changing patterns of life on Earth.
Alvarez, W. (2003). Comparing the evidence relevant to impact and flood basalt at times of major mass extinctions. Astrobiology, 3, 153-161.
AmphiWeb (2009). AmphibiaWeb: Information on amphibian biology and conservation. University of California, Berkeley, California. http://amphibiaweb.org/.
Atsma, A. J. (2009). The Theoi Project, Greek Mythology. Auckland, New Zealand. http://www.theoi.com.
Bambach, R. K. (2006). Phanerozoic biodiversity mass extinctions. Annual Review of Earth and Planetary Sciences, 34, 127-155.
Barlow, C. & Volk, T. (1992). Gaia and evolutionary biology. Bioscience, 42, 686-693.
Barnosky, A. D. (2008). Megafauna biomass tradeoff as a driver of Quaternary and future extinctions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 105, 11543-11548.
Benton, M. J. (1995). Diversification and extinction in the history of life. Science, 268, 52-58.
Benton, M. J. (2003). When Life Nearly Died: The Greatest Mass Extinction of All Time. Thames & Hudson, London.
Benton, M. J. (2009). The Red Queen and the Court Jester: species diversity and the role of biotic and abiotic factors through time. Science, 323, 728-732.
Bradshaw, C. J. A., Giam, X., Tan, H. T. W., Brook, B. W., Sodhi, N. S. (2008). Threat or invasive status in legumes is related to opposite extremes of the same ecological and life history attributes. Journal of Ecology, 96, 869-883.
Brook, B. W., Sodhi, N. S., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2008). Synergies among extinction drivers under global change. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 25, 453-460.
Brook, B. W., Traill, L. W., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2006). Minimum viable population size and global extinction risk are unrelated. Ecology Letters, 9, 375-382.
Brown, J. H., Ernest, S. K. M., Parody, J. M., Haskell, J. P. (2001). Regulation of diversity: maintenance of species richness in changing environments. Oecologia, 126, 321-332.
Caughley, G. (1994). Directions in conservation biology. Journal of Animal Ecology, 63, 215-244.
Conway-Morris, S. (1997). Palaeontology: Grasping the opportunities in the science of the twenty-first century. Geobios, 30, 895-904.
Conway-Morris, S. (1998). The evolution of diversity in ancient ecosystems: a review. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 353, 327-345.
Courchamp, F., Luděk, B., Gascoigne, B. (2008). Allee Effects in Ecology and Conservation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, United Kingdom.
Courtillot, V. (1999). Evolutionary Catastrophes: The Science of Mass Extinction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Crutzen, P. J. (2002). Geology of mankind: the Anthropocene. Nature, 415, 23.
Dawkins, R. (1982). The Extended Phenotype. W. H. Freeman, New York, NY.
Dawkins, R. (1989). The Selfish Gene. Second Edition edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Demetrius, L. (2000). Thermodynamics and evolution. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 206, 1-6.
Dobson, A., Lafferty, K. D., Kuris, A. M., Hechinger, R. F., Jetz, W. (2008). Homage to Linnaeus: How many parasites? How many hosts? Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 105, 11482-11489.
Doolittle, W. F. (1981). Is nature really motherly? CoEvolution Quarterly, 29, 58-65.
Ehrlich, P. (1991). Coevolution and its applicability to the Gaia hypothesis. In Scientists on Gaia (eds Schneider, S. H. & Boston, P. E.), pp. 19-22. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Ehrlich, P. R. & Pringle, R. M. (2008). Where does biodiversity go from here? A grim business-as-usual forecast and a hopeful portfolio of partial solutions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 105, 11579-11586.
Erwin, D. H. (1998). The end and the beginning: recoveries from mass extinctions. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 13, 344-349.
Erwin, D. H. (2001). Lessons from the past: biotic recoveries from mass extinctions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 98, 5399-5403.
Erwin, D. H. (2006). Extinction: How Life on Earth Nearly Ended 250 Million Years Ago. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Fagan, W. F. & Holmes, E. E. (2006). Quantifying the extinction vortex. Ecology Letters, 9, 51-60.
Fenchel, T. & Finlay, B. J. (2006). The diversity of microbes: resurgence of the phenotype. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 361, 1965-1973.
Field, I. C., Meekan, M. G., Buckworth, R. C., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2009). Susceptibility of sharks, rays and chimaeras to global extinction. Advances in Marine Biology, 56, doi:10.1016/S0065-2881(09)56004-X.
Frankham, R., Ballou, J. D., Briscoe, D. A. (2002). Introduction to Conservation Genetics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
Frost, D. R. (2009). Amphibian Species of the World: an Online Reference Version 5.3. American Museum of Natural History, New York. http://research.amnh.org/herpetology/amphibia/.
Gaston, K. J. (2000). Global patterns in biodiversity. Nature, 405, 220-227.
Gaston, K. J. (2008). Biodiversity and extinction: the importance of being common. Progress in Physical Geography, 32, 73-79.
Gaston, K. J. & Fuller, R. A. (2008). Commonness, population depletion and conservation biology. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23, 14-19.
Gill, F. (2002). Birds of the World: Recommended English Names. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Gomez, J. J., Goy, A., Barron, E. (2007). Events around the Triassic-Jurassic boundary in northern and eastern Spain: A review. Palaeogeography Palaeoclimatology Palaeoecology, 244, 89-110.
Gross, A. O. (1931). Banding the last heath hen. Bird Banding, 2, 99-105.
Hallam, A. (2005). Catastrophes and Lesser Calamities: The Causes of Mass Extinctions. Oxford University Press, New York.
Hallam, A. & Wignall, P. B. (1997). Mass Extinctions and Their Aftermath. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
Halliday, T. (1978). Vanishing Birds: Their Natural History and Conservation. 1st edn. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York.
Hanski, I. (1998). Metapopulation dynamics. Nature, 396, 41-49.
Hanski, I. (1999). Metapopulation Ecology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
Hawksworth, D. L. (1991). The fungal dimension of biodiversity: magnitude, significance, and conservation. Mycological Research, 95, 641-655.
Hoffman, A. (1989). What, if anything, are mass extinctions. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 325, 263-261.
Hoyle, F. and Wickramasinghe, N.C. (2000) Astronomical Origins of Life: Steps towards Panspermia (Kluwer Academic Press, USA).
Jablonski, D. (1989). The biology of mass extinction: a palaeontological view. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 325, 357-368.
Johnson, C. N. (1998). Species extinction and the relationship between distribution and abundance. Nature, 394, 272-274.
Johnson, J. & Dunn, P. (2006). Low genetic variation in the heath hen prior to extinction and implications for the conservation of prairie-chicken populations. Conservation Genetics, 7, 37-48.
Joseph, R. (2009a). Life on Earth came from other planets. Journal of Cosmology, 1, 1-56.
Joseph, R. (2009b). The evolution of Life from other planets. Journal of Cosmology, 1, 100-200.
Lawton, J. H. & May, R. M., eds. (1995). Extinction Rates. Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK.
Lenton, T. M. & Lovelock, J. E. (2000). Daisyworld is Darwinian: constraints on Adaptation are important for planetary self-regulation. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 206, 109-114.
Lovelock, J. (2006). The Revenge of Gaia. Penguin Books, London.
Lovelock, J. (2009). The Vanishing Face of Gaia: A Final Warning. Basic Books, New York, NY.
Lovelock, J. E. (1965). A physical basis for life detection experiments. Nature, 20, 568-570.
Lovelock, J. E. (1972). Gaia as seen through the atmosphere. Atmospheric Environment, 6, 579-580.
Lovelock, J. E. & Margulis, L. (1974). Atmospheric homeostasis by and for the biosphere - the Gaia hypothesis. Tellus, 26, 2-10.
Matheny, J. G. (2007). Reducing the risk of human extinction. Risk Analysis, 27, 1335-1344.
McKinney, M. L. (1998). On predicting biotic homogenization: species-area patterns in marine biota. Global Ecology and Biogeography Letters, 7, 297-301.
Melbourne, B. A. & Hastings, A. (2008). Extinction risk depends strongly on factors contributing to stochasticity. Nature, 454, 100-103.
Napier, W. M. (2004). A mechanism for interstellar panspermia. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, 348, 46-51. 18
Nee, S. & May, R. M. (1997). Extinction and the Loss of Evolutionary History. Science, 278, 692-694.
Novotny, V., Basset, Y., Miller, S. E., Weiblen, G. D., Bremer, B., Cizek, L., Drozd, P. (2002). Low host specificity of herbivorous insects in a tropical forest. Nature, 416, 841-844.
Pimm, S. L. & Raven, P. (2000). Extinction by numbers. Nature, 403, 843-845.
Pimm, S. L., Russell, G. J., Gittleman, J. L., Brooks, T. M. (1995). The future of biodiversity. Science, 269, 347-350.
Prance, G. T. (2001). Discovering the plant world. Taxon, 50, 345-359.
Purvis, A., Jones, K. E., Mace, G. M. (2000). Extinction. BioEssays, 22, 1123-1133.
Raup, D. M. (1986). Biological extinction in Earth history. Science, 231, 1528-1533.
Raup, D. M. (1991). Extinction: Bad Genes or Bad luck? W.W. Norton, New York.
Raup, D. M. (1994). The role of extinction in evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 91, 6758-6763.
Raup, D. M. & Sepkoski, J. J., Jr. (1986). Periodic extinction of families and genera. Science, 231, 833-836.
Sepkoski, J. J., Bambach, R. K., Raup, D. M., Valentine, J. W. (1981). Phanerozoic marine diversity and the fossil record. Nature, 293, 435-437.
Singh, J. S. (2002). The biodiversity crisis: a multifaceted review. Current Science, 82, 638-647.
Smith, F. D. M., May, R. M., Pellew, R., Johnson, T. H., Walter, K. R. (1993). How much do we know about the current extinction rate. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 8, 375-378.
Sodhi, N. S., Bickford, D., Diesmos, A. C., Lee, T. M., Koh, L. P., Brook, B. W., Sekercioglu, C. H., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2008a). Measuring the meltdown: drivers of global amphibian extinction and decline. PLoS ONE, 3, e1636.
Sodhi, N. S., Brook, B. W., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2009). Causes and consequences of species extinctions. In The Princeton Guide to Ecology (ed Levin, S. A.), pp. 514-520. Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey.
Sodhi, N. S., Koh, L. P., Peh, K. S.-H., Tan, H. T. W., Chazdon, R. L., Corlett, R. T., Lee, T. M., Colwell, R. K., Brook, B. W., Sekercioglu, C. H., Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2008b). Correlates of extinction proneness in tropical angiosperms. Diversity and Distributions, 14, 1-10.
Stenseth, N. C. (1979). Where have all the species gone? On the nature of extinction and the Red Queen Hypothesis. Oikos, 33, 196-227.
Van Valen, L. (1973). A new evolutionary law. Evolutionary Theory, 1, 1-30.
Volk, T. (2006). Real concerns, false gods. Nature, 440, 869-870.
Ward, P. (2009a). Gaia's evil twin. New Scientist, 202, 28-31.
Ward, P. (2009b). The Medea Hypothesis: Is Life on Earth Ultimately Self-Destructive? Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Ward, P. D. (1994). The End of Evolution: On Mass Extinctions and the Preservation of Biodiversity. Bantam, New York.
Watson, A. (2009). Final warning from a sceptical prophet. Nature, 458, 970-971.
Watson, A. J. & Lovelock, J. E. (1983). Biological homeostasis of the global environment: the parable of Daisyworld. Tellus, 35, 284-289.
Westing, A. H. (1981). A note on how many humans that have ever lived. Bioscience, 31, 523-524.
Whitfield, J. (2007). Survival of the likeliest? PLoS Biology, 5, e142 doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050142.
Wilson, D. E. & Reeder, D. M., eds. (2005). Mammal Species of the World: A Taxonomic and Geographic Reference, pp 2142. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, Maryland.
Wilson, D. S. & Sober, E. (1989). Reviving the superorganism. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 136, 337-356. 21
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Colonizing the Red Planet ISBN: 9780982955239 |
Sir Roger Penrose & Stuart Hameroff ISBN: 9780982955208 |
The Origins of LIfe ISBN: 9780982955215 |
Came From Other Planets ISBN: 9780974975597 |
Panspermia, Life ISBN: 9780982955222 |
Explaining the Origins of Life ISBN 9780982955291 |